My father didn’t like to spend money when he didn’t have to,
so when my mother expressed a wish for an automatic dishwasher, one day he
showed up with an old portable unit that some friends of ours got rid of when
they bought a newer model. It was a
big floor-model box on rollers, and you ran one hose to the kitchen sink and another
to the sink drain and plugged it into a wall outlet. It worked fine for a few
weeks. Then one day it refused to
drain. We opened the door and saw
all this dirty dishwater, so we bailed it out and I volunteered to fix it. Because I was cheaper than calling a
repairman, my father agreed to let me tear into the thing. After a lot of gross and messy work, I
found the problem: a toothpick had
lodged between the drain pump impeller and the housing. That little toothpick had jammed the
pump, and as a result the whole washer couldn’t drain.
I learned several things from that experience (not the least
of which was to avoid appliance repair as a future career). But the most important one was that
fairly small, common, almost unnoticeable things can have big negative
effects. And the things don’t need
to be physical ones at all. In
fact, immaterial things can make a lot more difference than any physical
object, especially if they are so widespread that you don’t notice them, like
fish who don’t realize it’s water that they’re swimming in. The little thing I’d like to draw your
attention to is nominalism.
The word “nominal” is often used by engineers to mean
“typical” or “according to the specifications.” But its original meaning is “relating to names.” Nominalism is a philosophical position
first proposed by William of Ockham (~1288 A. D. - ~1348). Until he came along, most philosophers
thought the word “apple,” for example, referred to a real and essential, though
immaterial, “appleness” that is shared by all things properly called
apples. However, William of Ockham
claimed that there was no such thing as appleness—the essence of what it is to
be an apple. Instead, “apple” is
just a name for certain kinds of
objects that we, in our human wisdom, have decided to call apples. In other words, he denied that there
are any universals—that is, essences
of things. There’s just a lot of
round red fruits out there that, for convenience, we have decided to group
under the name of “apple,” but in reality, all apples are different individuals
and there is nothing more to the word than the sum of all things called apples.
After William of Ockham proposed nominalism, the other philosophers
had to think of a name to call themselves, and the term they chose was
“realists.” A realist, in this
technical sense, thinks that there is indeed a universal concept, objective and
independent of our minds, which in English is denoted by the word “apple.” These concepts, which the moderate
realist Aristotle called essences,
are as objectively real as a bank account. A bank account is not a material thing, though there may be
material records of it. A bank
account is a non-material concept, and so are the concepts of “apple,” “tree,”
“horse,” and “man.”
Unless you are aware of this historical controversy, as a
typical 21st-century person you probably think and act as a nominalist most of
the time. For example, if you
agree with the words of the 1992 U. S. Supreme Court decision in Planned Parenthood vs. Casey that “At
the heart of liberty is the right to define one's own concept of existence, of
meaning, of the universe, and of the mystery of human life,” you are a
nominalist, because defining is what a nominalist does. First comes the name, then come the
items to be grouped under that name.
But the namer is always in charge, and things can be arbitrarily
regrouped by the namer to suit one’s convenience. As the philosopher Richard Weaver has pointed out, an
important consequence of nominalism is that “if words no longer correspond to
objective realities, it seems no great wrong to take liberties with
words.” So, for example, the
genocide of Jews by Nazi Germany in World War II is euphemized to “the final
solution.”
Engineers are perhaps less apt to fall into the grosser
errors of nominalism, because we have frequent encounters with objective
reality. If a computer chip you
design doesn’t work, calling it by a different name isn’t going to make it start
working. But even the way
engineers use logic has been affected by nominalism. The digital logic that all digital computers use is based on
symbolic logic devised by George Boole, a nineteenth-century mathematician
whose hope was to reduce all logic to symbols. The trouble is, symbolic logic assumes that nominalism is
true, and throws out a great deal of material that traditional Aristotelian
logic relied on, including the notion that understanding is a uniquely human
power essential to right thinking.
But if everybody uses nominalist logic that can be expressed by Boole’s
“boolean algebra,” we have reduced our thought processes to those that can be
done by computers. This is an
important source of the idea put forth by artificial intelligence proponents
that the brain is really nothing more than an advanced wet computer. If we can’t make computers act like
humans, we’ll reduce humans to the point that they act like computers.
Let’s hope that doesn’t happen. Regular readers of this blog may have noted that I try to
approach philosophical matters from an Aristotelian perspective that moves from
the real, objective world to the world of thoughts. Nominalism tempts us to do the opposite: to define things the way we want them
to be, and then look for pieces of reality that fit our preconceived
notions. I think engineers of all
people should be aware of the dangers of nominalism. Realism is more than just being practical; it means
realizing that there is more to the world than we can possibly understand or
control, and the proper attitude toward nature is one of humility. Otherwise, like that toothpick in the
dishwasher, nominalism can throw a whole culture out of whack.
Sources: The quotation by Richard Weaver is from
his 1948 book Ideas Have Consequences
(Univ. of Chicago Press), p. 7. I
was inspired to write about nominalism and realism by reading one of the few
logic textbooks in print which employ realist Aristotelian logic rather than
symbolic logic as its basis: Peter
Kreeft’s Socratic Logic (South Bend,
Indiana: St. Augustine’s Press,
2004).
A very lovely post. Been reading this blog for well on a year now and always enjoy it. Thanks for writing on such a diversity of topics!
ReplyDelete